490
Views
734
Downloads
5
Crossref
N/A
WoS
3
Scopus
N/A
CSCD
Weaponized in support of deregulation and self-regulation, “ethics” is increasingly identified with technology companies’ self-regulatory efforts and with shallow appearances of ethical behavior. So-called “ethics washing” by tech companies is on the rise, prompting criticism and scrutiny from scholars and the tech community. The author defines “ethics bashing” as the parallel tendency to trivialize ethics and moral philosophy. Underlying these two attitudes are a few misunderstandings: (1) philosophy is understood in opposition and as alternative to law, political representation, and social organizing; (2) philosophy and “ethics” are perceived as formalistic, vulnerable to instrumentalization, and ontologically flawed; and (3) moral reasoning is portrayed as mere “ivory tower” intellectualization of complex problems that need to be dealt with through other methodologies. This article argues that the rhetoric of ethics and morality should not be reductively instrumentalized, either by the industry in the form of “ethics washing”, or by scholars and policy-makers in the form of “ethics bashing”. Grappling with the role of philosophy and ethics requires moving beyond simplification and seeing ethics as a mode of inquiry that facilitates the evaluation of competing tech policy strategies. We must resist reducing moral philosophy’s role and instead must celebrate its special worth as a mode of knowledge-seeking and inquiry. Far from mandating self-regulation, moral philosophy facilitates the scrutiny of various modes of regulation, situating them in legal, political, and economic contexts. Moral philosophy indeed can explainin the relationship between technology and other worthy goals and can situate technology within the human, the social, and the political.
Weaponized in support of deregulation and self-regulation, “ethics” is increasingly identified with technology companies’ self-regulatory efforts and with shallow appearances of ethical behavior. So-called “ethics washing” by tech companies is on the rise, prompting criticism and scrutiny from scholars and the tech community. The author defines “ethics bashing” as the parallel tendency to trivialize ethics and moral philosophy. Underlying these two attitudes are a few misunderstandings: (1) philosophy is understood in opposition and as alternative to law, political representation, and social organizing; (2) philosophy and “ethics” are perceived as formalistic, vulnerable to instrumentalization, and ontologically flawed; and (3) moral reasoning is portrayed as mere “ivory tower” intellectualization of complex problems that need to be dealt with through other methodologies. This article argues that the rhetoric of ethics and morality should not be reductively instrumentalized, either by the industry in the form of “ethics washing”, or by scholars and policy-makers in the form of “ethics bashing”. Grappling with the role of philosophy and ethics requires moving beyond simplification and seeing ethics as a mode of inquiry that facilitates the evaluation of competing tech policy strategies. We must resist reducing moral philosophy’s role and instead must celebrate its special worth as a mode of knowledge-seeking and inquiry. Far from mandating self-regulation, moral philosophy facilitates the scrutiny of various modes of regulation, situating them in legal, political, and economic contexts. Moral philosophy indeed can explainin the relationship between technology and other worthy goals and can situate technology within the human, the social, and the political.
P. Nemitz, Constitutional democracy and technology in the age of artificial intelligence, Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society A, vol. 376, no. 2133, p. 20180089, 2018.
J. Metcalf, E. Moss, and D. Boyd, Owning ethics: Corporate logics, Sillicon Valley, and the institutionalization of ethics, Social Research:An International Quarterly, vol. 82, no. 2, pp. 449–476, 2019.
A. L. Hoffmann, Where fairness fails: Data, algorithms, and the limits of antidiscrimination discourse, Information Communication and Society, vol. 22, no. 7, pp. 900–915, 2019.
O. Tene and J. Polonetsky, A theory of creepy: Technology, privacy, and shifting social norms, Yale Journal of Law,and Technology, vol. 16, no. 1, p. 2, 2014.
B. J. Grosz, D. G. Grant, K. Vredenburgh, J. Behrends, L. Hu, A. Simmons, and J. Waldo, Embedded EthiCS: Integrating ethics across CS Education, Communications of the ACM, vol. 62, no. 8, pp. 54–61, 2019.
P. Foot, The problem of abortion and the doctrine of the double effect, Oxford Review, vol. 5, pp. 5–15, 1967.
E. Awad, S. Dsouza, R. Kim, J. Schulz, J. Henrich, A. Shariff, J-F. Bonnefon, and I. Rahwan, The moral machine experiment, Nature, vol. 563, no. 7729, pp. 59–64, 2018.
E. Awad, S. Dsouza, A. Shariff, J. -F. Bonnefon, and I. Rahwan, Crowdsourcing moral machines, Communications of the ACM, vol. 63, no. 3, pp. 48–55, 2020.
B. Mittelstadt, Principles alone cannot guarantee ethical AI, Nature Machine Intelligence, vol. 1, pp. 501–507, 2019.
C. Baumann, Was Hegel an authoritarian thinker? Reading Hegel's Philosophy of History on the basis of his metaphysics, Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie, vol. 103, no. 1, pp. 120–147, 2019.
J. Zigon, Moral breakdown and the ethical demand: A theoretical framework for an anthropology of moralities, Anthropological Theory, vol. 7, no. 2, pp. 131–150, 2007.
J. Habermas, Reconciliation through the public use of reason: Remarks on John Rawls's political liberalism, The Journal of Philosophy, vol. 92, no. 3, pp. 109–131, 1995.
K. Dotson, How is this paper philosophy? Comparative Philosophy, vol. 3, no. 1, pp. 3–29, 2012.
L. Winner, Do artifacts have politics? Daedalus, vol. 109, no. 1, pp. 121–136, 1980.
L. Floridi, Translating principles into practices of digital ethics: Five risks of being unethical, Philosophy and Technology, vol. 32, pp. 185–193, 2019.
J. Balkin, Free speech is a triangle, Colorado Law Review, vol. 118, p. 201, 2018.
E. Douek, Facebook’s “oversight board:” Move fast with stable infrastructure and humility, North Carolina Journal of Law and Technology, vol. 21, no. 1, pp. 1–78, 2019.
T. Kadri and K. Klonick, Facebook v. Sullivan: Building constitutional law for online speech, Southern California Law Review, vol. 93, p. 37, 2019.
E. Bietti thanks Jeff Behrends, Yochai Benkler, Brian Berkey, Reuben Binns, Mark Budolfson, Urs Gasser, Ben Green, Lily Hu, Lucas Stanczyk, Luke Stark, Jonathan Zittrain, and some anonymous reviewers for their valuable input on this article.
The articles published in this open access journal are distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).