807
Views
703
Downloads
3
Crossref
N/A
WoS
4
Scopus
N/A
CSCD
What are the consequences of the language we use for technology, and, how we describe the frameworks regarding technology and its creation, use, and deployment? The language used to describe technology has the possibility to deceive and be abusive. How language is used demonstrates what can occur when one party is able to assert linguistic power over another. The way in which organizations frame their relationships with technology is one such power asymmetry. This article examines the complications of the imagery used for ethics in technology. Then, the author offers a brief overview of how language influences our perceptions. The frames used to describe phenomena, including ethical frameworks and technology, allow for the creation of heuristics, or shortcuts that are “good enough” for understanding what is being described and for decision-making. Therefore, descriptions matter for relaying meaning and constructing narratives related to ethical uses of technical systems. After this, the author investigates what we mean by ethics and the codes that corporate, governmental, and other organizations use to depict how they understand their relationship to the technology they create and deploy. The author explores three examples of frames of ethics and descriptions of technology, which though appearing progressive, once understood holistically, fail to adequately describe technology and its possible impact. The author ends this article with a discussion of the complexity of describing and communicating ethical uses of technology.
What are the consequences of the language we use for technology, and, how we describe the frameworks regarding technology and its creation, use, and deployment? The language used to describe technology has the possibility to deceive and be abusive. How language is used demonstrates what can occur when one party is able to assert linguistic power over another. The way in which organizations frame their relationships with technology is one such power asymmetry. This article examines the complications of the imagery used for ethics in technology. Then, the author offers a brief overview of how language influences our perceptions. The frames used to describe phenomena, including ethical frameworks and technology, allow for the creation of heuristics, or shortcuts that are “good enough” for understanding what is being described and for decision-making. Therefore, descriptions matter for relaying meaning and constructing narratives related to ethical uses of technical systems. After this, the author investigates what we mean by ethics and the codes that corporate, governmental, and other organizations use to depict how they understand their relationship to the technology they create and deploy. The author explores three examples of frames of ethics and descriptions of technology, which though appearing progressive, once understood holistically, fail to adequately describe technology and its possible impact. The author ends this article with a discussion of the complexity of describing and communicating ethical uses of technology.
F. Ferreira, K. G. D. Bailey, and V. Ferraro, Good-enough representations in language comprehension, Current Direction in Psychological Science, vol. 11, no. 1, pp. 11–15, 2002.
F. Ferreira and N. D. Patson, The ‘Good Enough’ approach to language comprehension, Language and Linguistics Compass, vol. 1, no. 1&2, pp. 71–83, 2007.
A. Appadurai, Disjuncture and difference in the global cultural economy, Theory, vol. 7, no. 2, pp. 295–310, 1990.
C. H. de Vreese, News framing: Theory and typology, Information Design Journal, vol. 13, no. 1, pp. 51–62, 2005.
R. M. Entman, Framing: Toward clarification of a fractured paradigm, Journal of Communication, vol. 43, no. 4, pp. 51–58, 1993.
M. Edelman, Contestable categories and public opinion, Political Communication, vol. 10, no. 3, pp. 231–242, 1993.
D. A. Scheufele, Framing as a theory of media effects, Journal of Communication, vol. 49, no. 1, pp. 103–122, 1999.
D. A. Scheufele, Agenda-setting, priming, and framing revisited: Another look at cognitive effects of political communication, Mass Communicaiton and Society, vol. 3, no. 2&3, pp. 297–316, 2000.
P. M. Napoli, Revisiting ‘mass communication’ and the ‘work’ of the audience in the new media environment, Media,Culture&Society, vol. 32, no. 3, pp. 505–516, 2010.
M. A. Cacciatore, D. A. Scheufele, and S. Iyengar, The end of framing as we know it … and the future of media effects, Mass Communication and Society, vol. 19, no. 1, pp. 7–23, 2016.
D. Chong and J. N. Druckman, Framing theory, Annual Review of Political Science, vol. 10, no. 1, pp. 103–126, 2007.
D. A. Scheufele and D. Tewksbury, Framing, agenda setting, and priming: The evolution of three media effects models, Journal of Communication, vol. 57, no. 1, pp. 9–20, 2007.
P. V. Lewis, Defining ‘business ethics’: Like nailing jello to a wall, Journal of Business Ethics, vol. 4, no. 5, pp. 377–383, 1985.
J. Fischer, Social responsibility and ethics: Clarifying the concepts, Journal of Business Ethics, vol. 52, no. 4, pp. 381–390, 2004.
D. Berdichevsky and E. Neuenschwander, Toward an ethics of persuasive technology, Communications of the ACM, vol. 42, no. 5, pp. 51–58, 1999.
C. A. Ellwood, The sociological basis of ethics, Int. J. Ethics, vol. 20, no. 3, pp. 314–329, 1910.
G. Wood and M. Rimmer, Codes of ethics: What are they really and what should they be? International Journal of Value-Bsaed Management, vol. 16, no. 2, pp. 181–195, 2003.
M. S. Frankel, Professional codes: Why, how, and with what impact? Journal of Business Ethics, vol. 8, no. 2&3, pp. 109–115, 1989.
G. Vinten, Business ethics: Busybody or corporate conscience? Managerial Auditing Journal, vol. 5, no. 2, pp. 4–11, 1990.
P. Sundstrom, Interpreting the notion that technology is value-neutral, Medicine Health Care and Philosophy, vol. 1, no. 1, pp. 41–45, 1998.
L. Winner, Do artifacts have politics? Daedalus, vol. 109, no. 1, pp. 121–136, 1980.
M. B. Kent, Pavesich, property and privacy: The common origins of property rights and privacy rights in Georgia, John Marshall Law Journal, vol. 2, no. 1, 2009.
J. B. Baron, Rescuing the bundle-of-rights metaphor in property law, University of Cincinnati Law Review, vol. 82, no. 1, pp. 57–102, 2014.
D. R. Johnson, Reflections on the bundle of rights lecture, Vermont Law Review, vol. 32, pp. 247–272, 2007.
C. I. Harris, Whiteness as property, Harvard Law Review, vol. 106, no. 8, pp. 1707–1791, 1993.
M. Armstrong, African Americans and property ownership: Creating our own meanings, redefining our relationships, African-American Law and Policy Report, vol. 1, pp. 79–88, 1994.
J. Karat, Evolving the sope of uer-cntered dsign, Communication of the ACM, vol. 40, no. 7, pp. 33–38, 1997.
J. Gulliksen, B. Göransson, I. Boivie, S. Blomkvist, J. Persson, and Å. Cajander, Key principles for user-centred systems design, Behaviour and Information Technology, vol. 22, no. 6, pp. 397–409, 2003.
T. Miaskiewicz and K. A. Kozar, Personas and user-centered design: How can personas benefit product design processes? Design Studies, vol. 32, no. 5, pp. 417–430, 2011.
A. L. Massanari, Designing for imaginary friends: Information architecture, personas and the politics of user-centered design, New Media and Society, vol. 12, no. 3, pp. 401–416, 2010.
C. Schwarz-Plaschg, The power of analogies for imagining and governing emerging technologies, NanoEthics, vol. 12, no. 2, pp. 139–153, 2018.
J. E. McNealy would like to acknowledge the collective wisdom of the Ethical Tech Collective and those who participate in the Ethical Tech Working Group.
The articles published in this open access journal are distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).